The Good Life and How to Live It
Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics, Book I

Picture of <b>Wes Siscoe</b><br><small>Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Bowling Green State University</small>
Wes Siscoe
Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Bowling Green State University

Table of Contents

Warm-Up: So You Want to Live a Good Life?

We all want to live good lives. No one wakes up in the morning and decides that they want to live a purposeless, empty, meaningless existence. But what exactly does it mean to live a good life? How will we know when we achieve it? There are many different things that are thought to contribute to the good life – wealth, happiness, deep friendships, and passionate romance are all examples. While these all might be involved in living a good life, we are interested in the core of the good life. What is the most fundamental thing that makes a life good? Today, we’ll consider Aristotle’s answer to that question, but before we do that, weigh in on the following poll to cast your vote for what makes a life good.

Poll

Loading poll ...
Coming Soon
Which of the following is most essential to living a good life?
{{ row.Answer_Title }} {{row.tsp_result_percent}} % {{row.Answer_Votes}} {{row.Answer_Votes}} ( {{row.tsp_result_percent}} % ) {{ tsp_result_no }}

Introduction

Aristotle (384-322 BC) was a Greek philosopher who studied under Plato and went on to be one of the most influential thinkers to ever live. Simply called “The Philosopher” by Thomas Aquinas and others in the medieval period, Aristotle’s views would eventually be synthesized with Christian theology, laying the intellectual foundation for later scholarly developments in Western Europe.

You’ll be reading a selection from Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Comprised of ten books (or what we think of as chapters), the Nicomachean Ethics lays out Aristotle’s moral philosophy, and is widely considered to be one of the most important works of ancient philosophy and a foundational text for the area of philosophy called virtue ethics. If you’re interested, the full text of the Nicomachean Ethics can be found here.

Key Concepts

Final Good – A good that we pursue for its own sake. Common examples of final goods include happiness, knowledge, and friendship

Instrumental Good – A good that we pursue for the sake of some other good. A common example is money, as money allows us to purchase other kinds of goods

Eudaimonia – Frequently translated as ‘happiness’, eudaimonia means the attainment of active human flourishing, and is the end Aristotle identifies as humanity’s highest final good

Function – The characteristic activity of a given thing which makes it what it is. The function of a knife is cutting, while the function of a heart is to pump blood

Virtue – The consistent and reliable tendency to perform one’s function excellently. When a person has a certain virtue, like courage, they have spent time developing the habit, in this case reacting to danger well, using their human abilities. The virtues then make it possible for us to live a life of flourishing

Hitting the Target

Aristotle begins by considering the difference between two kinds of goals, those that we aim to achieve because they help us accomplish other goals and those that we aim at for their own sake.

Book 1.1-2

Every art and every kind of inquiry, and likewise every act and purpose, seems to aim at some good: and so it has been well said that the good is that at which everything aims.

But a difference is observable among these aims or ends. What is aimed at is sometimes the exercise of a faculty, sometimes a certain result beyond that exercise. And where there is an end beyond the act, there the result is better than the exercise of the faculty.

Now since there are many kinds of actions and many arts and sciences, it follows that there are many ends also; e.g. health is the end of medicine, ships of shipbuilding, victory of the art of war, and wealth of economy […]

If then in what we do there be some end which we wish for on its own account, choosing all the others as means to this, but not every end without exception as a means to something else (for so we should go on ad infinitum, and desire would be left void and objectless),—this evidently will be the good or the best of all things. And surely from a practical point of view it much concerns us to know this good; for then, like archers shooting at a definite mark, we shall be more likely to attain what we want.

Connection

Final vs. Instrumental Goods

In this passage, Aristotle points out that all of the actions we perform aim at some kind of good. When we go shopping, we aim to buy food. When we go to school, we aim to acquire knowledge. And when we apply for jobs, we aim to be employed. Some of the goods we aim at are helpful because they help us to pursue other goods. We want a job, so that we can make money. And we want to make money because then we can buy food. And we want to buy food so that we can eat. For this reason, all of these goods – the job, the money, the food – are potential examples of instrumental goods. They are good because of the other goods they help us obtain.

But Aristotle points out that this chain cannot go on forever. If every good we seek is only good because it leads to something else, then this process of aiming at one thing so we can get another would never end. Instead, Aristotle thinks that there must be some final good that we pursue for its own sake. This final good helps explain why we pursue instrumental goods in the first place. Ultimately, we are trying to reach some final good or goods that make it worth pursuing things like a job, money, and food.

Don't Worry, Be Happy

Having established that, when we act, we are ultimately aiming at a final good, Aristotle asks what that final good might be. And that good is happiness!

Book 1.4

Since — to resume — all knowledge and all purpose aims at some good, what is this which we say is the aim of Politics; or, in other words, what is the highest of all realizable goods? As to its name, I suppose nearly all men are agreed; for the masses and the men of culture alike declare that it is happiness, and hold that to “live well” or to “do well” is the same as to be “happy.”

But they differ as to what this happiness is, and the masses do not give the same account of it as the philosophers. The former take it to be something palpable and plain, as pleasure or wealth or fame; one man holds it to be this, and another that, and often the same man is of different minds at different times,—after sickness it is health, and in poverty it is wealth; while when they are impressed with the consciousness of their ignorance, they admire most those who say grand things that are above their comprehension.

Main Idea

Eudaimonia

What is our final good, the thing that we do everything else for the sake of? Aristotle says that good is eudaimonia, translated here as ‘happiness’. But it is important to note that what we think of as happiness can distort what Aristotle is saying here. When we say, “I am happy”, we often mean that we are feeling a particular emotion or having a certain kind of experience. But when Aristotle talks about eudaimonia, he has a broader concept in mind. He wants to know, not what makes us psychologically happy, but what makes our lives go well. He wants to know what it takes to live a flourishing, well-lived life, and so we can also translate eudaimonia as ‘flourishing’. So when you are considering Aristotle’s arguments, think about not just what it takes to experience a feeling of happiness, but what it takes to live a flourishing life.

Is Happiness Pleasure?

As Aristotle said at the end of the previous section, even though we agree that happiness in the form of flourishing is ultimately what we are aiming at, there is a considerable amount of disagreement about what a flourishing human life is like. To make progress on this question, Aristotle considers some popular proposals for what happiness might be like, starting with a life of pleasure.

Book 1.5

It seems that men not unreasonably take their notions of the good or happiness from the lives actually led, and that the masses who are the least refined suppose it to be pleasure, which is the reason why they aim at nothing higher than the life of enjoyment […]

The mass of men show themselves utterly slavish in their preference for the life of brute beasts, but their views receive consideration because many of those in high places have the tastes of Sardanapalus.

The first option that Aristotle considers for a flourishing life is a life focused on enjoying various pleasures like food and sex. While he doesn’t think that these things are bad in themselves, he does think that a life that only focuses on these things is too much like that of lower animals to be what human happiness is like. In fact, this contrast between humans and other animals will play a large role below in Aristotle’s ultimate conclusions about happiness when he considers the unique function of humans.

Objection

Epicurus and the Life of Pleasure

Does Aristotle give the life of pleasure its due? While it may be true that pursuing pleasure like lower animals do will not lead to a life of flourishing, there are other philosophers who have defended a more nuanced view of the role that pleasure plays in a happy human life. Epicurus held that pleasure is the only final good and that all other things we pursue are merely instrumental goods on the way to more pleasure, but he didn’t think of pleasure simply in terms of indulging our appetites for food and sex. Instead, Epicurus thought that the philosophical life would lead to more pleasure than a life of partying, leaving open the possibility that there is more to be said in favor of the life of pleasure.

Is Happiness Fame?

If pleasure isn’t the ultimate goal of a flourishing life, then it must be something else. Next, Aristotle considers whether the final end of the happy life is to be honored by others.

Book I.9-10

Men of refinement with a practical turn prefer honour; for I suppose we may say that honour is the aim of the statesman’s life.

But this seems too superficial to be the good we are seeking: for it appears to depend upon those who give rather than upon those who receive it; while we have a presentiment that the good is something that is peculiarly a man’s own and can scarce be taken away from him.

Moreover, these men seem to pursue honour in order that they may be assured of their own excellence,—at least, they wish to be honoured by men of sense, and by those who know them, and on the ground of their virtue or excellence. It is plain, then, that in their view, at any rate, virtue or excellence is better than honour; and perhaps we should take this to be the end of the statesman’s life, rather than honour.

Argument

Fame Follows the Crowd

Here, Aristotle considers whether the flourishing human life might be found in being famous. He points out, though, that those who acquire fame and honor are always famous and honored for something

Premise 1: Fame and honor are given to a person for some characteristic they possess

Premise 2: If fame and honor are given to a person for some characteristic they possess, then there is a characteristic that is more valuable than fame and honor

Premise 3: If there is a characteristic that is more valuable than fame or honor, then fame and honor cannot be the highest good

Conclusion: Fame and honor cannot be the highest good

The athlete who can sell out a stadium is famous for their athletic ability, and the soldier who receives the medal of honor is honored for their service and their bravery. But if we honor these individuals because of their character or talent, it must be that character or talent that is ultimately valuable, not the fame that comes along with it. From this, Aristotle concludes that fame and honor are not essential to the flourishing life, but that we must continue our search for what happiness consists of.

Is Happiness Virtue?

In the last passage, Aristotle mentions virtue as one of the things that can make a man worthy of honor. And this does seem to be a strong candidate. When we think of someone who has strong character – that is compassionate, honest, loyal, and just – we tend to think of them as flourishing people. So maybe this is what Aristotle has in mind?

Book 1.5

But virtue or excellence also appears too incomplete to be what we want; for it seems that a man might have virtue and yet be asleep or be inactive all his life, and, moreover, might meet with the greatest disasters and misfortunes; and no one would maintain that such a man is happy, except for argument’s sake.

Surprisingly, Aristotle does not say that flourishing consists in being a virtuous person (though we will see reason to qualify this position later on). Instead, he points out that someone could be virtuous but not living a flourishing life due to inactivity or bad luck. If someone is a virtuous person but falls into a coma, we would not say that they are living a flourishing life. So even though virtue will be an important part of how Aristotle thinks about happiness, simply being a virtuous person is not enough to capture his full account of eudaimonia.

Is Happiness Wealth?

Having ruled out other possibilities, Aristotle then turns to wealth. Earlier, we pointed out that some goods are final while others are merely instrumental. Final goods are those we want for their own sake, while instrumental goods are only desirable because of the other things they can help us acquire. Here, Aristotle emphasizes that money is only an instrumental good.

Book 1.5

As for the money-making life, it is something quite contrary to nature; and wealth evidently is not the good of which we are in search, for it is merely useful as a means to something else. So we might rather take pleasure and virtue or excellence to be ends than wealth; for they are chosen on their own account. But it seems that not even they are the end, though much breath has been wasted in attempts to show that they are.

Money is an instrumental good, because we want it for the things it can help us get, whether that is food, fame, or a fancy car. If your dollars tomorrow became worthless and you couldn’t buy anything with them, then money would cease to be valuable. But because money is an instrumental good, it can’t be the final end we are seeking. The best money could do is help us buy something that makes us happy, but it cannot make us flourishing people on its own.

Function, Function, What's Your Function?

If Aristotle is right that happiness is the final good that we are all aiming at, it is worth knowing more about what happiness is. In this section, Aristotle elaborates on happiness not by considering the kinds of things that give us happiness and joy. Remember, he is not working with just a psychological understanding of happiness. Instead, Aristotle thinks that what it is to flourish is tightly connected to our purpose or function. If we are performing our function well, that is when we are truly flourishing.

Book I.7

But perhaps the reader thinks that though no one will dispute the statement that happiness is the best thing in the world, yet a still more precise definition of it is needed.

This will best be gained, I think, by asking, What is the function of man? For as the goodness and the excellence of a piper or a sculptor, or the practiser of any art, and generally of those who have any function or business to do, lies in that function, so man’s good would seem to lie in his function, if he has one.

But can we suppose that, while a carpenter and a cobbler has a function and a business of his own, man has no business and no function assigned him by nature? Nay, surely as his several members, eye and hand and foot, plainly have each his own function, so we must suppose that man also has some function over and above all these.

What then is it? Life evidently he has in common even with the plants, but we want that which is peculiar to him. We must exclude, therefore, the life of mere nutrition and growth. Next to this comes the life of sense; but this too he plainly shares with horses and cattle and all kinds of animals. There remains then the life whereby he acts—the life of his rational nature, with its two sides or divisions, one rational as obeying reason, the other rational as having and exercising reason […]

Man’s function then being, as we say, a kind of life—that is to say, exercise of his faculties and action of various kinds with reason—the good man’s function is to do this well and beautifully [or nobly]. But the function of anything is done well when it is done in accordance with the proper excellence of that thing.

If this be so the result is that the good of man is exercise of his faculties in accordance with excellence or virtue, or, if there be more than one, in accordance with the best and most complete virtue.

But there must also be a full term of years for this exercise; for one swallow or one fine day does not make a spring, nor does one day or any small space of time make a blessed or happy man.

After eliminating a number of options for the happy life, Aristotle here begins to give his own account. According to Aristotle, the final good which we aim at is “exercise of our faculties in accordance with excellence or virtue,” and this is what leads to a flourishing or happy life. But wait a second. Didn’t Aristotle previously say that virtue is too incomplete to characterize the good life? Notice before that Aristotle said before that virtue wasn’t enough for flourishing, since a virtuous person could fall into a coma and be unable to exercise their virtues. But here, Aristotle says that exercising virtue is the key to flourishing, which avoids the previous difficulty.

Argument

The Function Argument

In this passage, Aristotle draws a connection between when we say that something is good and when it fulfills its function. Knives are made for cutting, and so good knives are ones that cut well. Likewise, hammers are made for pounding in nails, and thus good hammers are those that are well-suited for the purpose of pounding nails. Aristotle then considers what our function is, what sort of thing humans are designed to do. He argues that the function unique to humans is living rationally, or living in accord with reason, making this a key part of what it is to live a good life.

Premise 1: If a human lives a good life, then he performs his function well or excellently.

Premise 2: The function of every human being is to consistently think and act rationally.

Conclusion: If a human lives a good life, then they do an excellent job of consistently thinking and acting rationally.

Aristotle motivates the second premise by considering what we have in common with other creatures. He considers, for example, whether our function is just being a live organism, but he points out that plants are also live organisms. He then asks whether our function is to be sentient, but other kinds of animals like horses and oxen are also sentient. This leads him to the conclusion that our rationality, and the fact that we can reason about the good, is what sets us apart from other kinds of living organisms, giving us a distinctive function that sets us apart from the rest of the animal kingdom.

Can You Only Be Happy When You're Dead?

In the previous passage, Aristotle said that it is not possible to flourish, or be happy, for just a single moment. Instead, whether someone is fulfilling their purpose or function is something that can only be seen over the course of a life. For this reason, Aristotle had concluded that “to be happy takes a complete lifetime”. But if this is true, does that mean someone can only be happy after they’re dead, only after we know how their entire life went? Let’s see what Aristotle says.

Book I.9-10

For, as we said, happiness requires not only perfect excellence or virtue, but also a full term of years for its exercise. For our circumstances are liable to many changes and to all sorts of chances, and it is possible that he who is now most prosperous will in his old age meet with great disasters, as is told of Priam in the tales of Troy; and a man who is thus used by fortune and comes to a miserable end cannot be called happy […]

Are we, then, to call no man happy as long as he lives, but to wait for the end, as Solon said? And, supposing we have to allow this, do we mean that he actually is happy after he is dead? Surely that is absurd, especially for us who say that happiness is a kind of activity or life […]

We reply that it cannot be right thus to follow fortune. For it is not in this that our weal or woe lies; but, as we said, though good fortune is needed to complete man’s life, yet it is the excellent employment of his powers that constitutes his happiness, as the reverse of this constitutes his misery.

But the discussion of this difficulty leads to a further confirmation of our account. For nothing human is so constant as the excellent exercise of our faculties. The sciences themselves seem to be less abiding. And the highest of these exercises are the most abiding, because the happy are occupied with them most of all and most continuously (for this seems to be the reason why we do not forget how to do them).

The happy man, then, as we define him, will have this required property of permanence, and all through life will preserve his character; for he will be occupied continually, or with the least possible interruption, in excellent deeds and excellent speculations; and, whatever his fortune be, he will take it in the noblest fashion, and bear himself always and in all things suitably, since he is truly good.

Here, Aristotle says that someone can be happy even if they do not know how their life will end up. This is because someone can be virtuous even when they face misfortune. As Aristotle says, the virtuous person will “bear changes of fortune most nobly, and with perfect propriety in every way”. Thus, whether or not someone is virtuous, and therefore whether or not they are flourishing, can be revealed even in the moments that their life is going poorly due to circumstances beyond their control.

The Ultimate Cliffhanger: What is Virtue?

Aristotle has already mentioned that happiness, and the good human life, is the one lived in accordance with virtue. But he hasn’t said too much about the nature of virtue or what the specific virtues are. Setting the stage for his more detailed discussion of virtue in the rest of the Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle gives us just a taste here of a few intellectual and moral virtues.

Book I.13

Since happiness is an exercise of the vital faculties in accordance with perfect virtue or excellence, we will now inquire about virtue or excellence; for this will probably help us in our inquiry about happiness […]

We speak of intellectual excellences and of moral excellences; wisdom and understanding and prudence we call intellectual, liberality and temperance we call moral virtues or excellences. When we are speaking of a man’s moral character we do not say that he is wise or intelligent, but that he is gentle or temperate. But we praise the wise man, too, for his habit of mind or trained faculty; and a habit or trained faculty that is praiseworthy is what we call an excellence or virtue.

Connection

Virtue Ethics

At the end of Book I, Aristotle turns to discuss the virtues, a topic that will occupy much of the rest of the Nicomachean Ethics. Because of his focus on the virtues, Aristotle is now one of the primary influences for contemporary philosophers working on virtue ethics. Along with taking the virtues to give us insight into how to live good lives, virtue ethicists also think that virtues like justice, honesty, temperance, and humility can help us determine what we should do and the kind of people we should be. For this reason, proponents of virtue ethics put an emphasis on developing the virtues through habitual practice rather than just following a list of moral rules.

Summary

In Book I of the Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle gives us a broad view of what he thinks it means to live a good life. For Aristotle, the good life is one in which we develop and exercise the distinctive human ability to think and act rationally. Such a life, on Aristotle’s view, is a happy or flourishing life. In the rest of the Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle will fill in this more general picture, discussing the particular virtues that it takes to fulfill our unique human nature.

Video

For a recap of Book I, and for a bit of the big picture of how Aristotle thinks about human flourishing and the virtues in the Nicomachean Ethics, check out this video on the Good Life in Aristotle:

Want to Learn More?

For a more complete picture of what it means to live well, keep on reading Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, including his thinking about the moral virtues (Books II-V), the intellectual virtues (Book VI), and friendship (Books VIII-IX). And for more about virtue ethics, the area of ethics that develops Aristotle’s insights about the moral life, check out this essay on “Virtue Ethics” from 1000-Word Philosophy.

Acknowledgements

This work has been adapted from The Nicomachean Ethics, a title from the eCampusOntario Public Domain Core Collection. This work is in the public domain. All images were created using Midjourney and are the property of the Philosophy Teaching Library.

Citation

Siscoe, Robert Weston. 2023. “The Good Life and How to Live It: Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, Book I.” The Philosophy Teaching Library. Edited by Robert Weston Siscoe, <https://philolibrary.crc.nd.edu/article/the-good-life-how-to-live-it/>

Key Concept

Occasionalism — a theory claiming that God is the only true cause of changes in the world. For example, when you high-five me, you’re not really the cause of the stinging sensation I experience. God is the cause. Your high five is just the occasion on which God causes it.     

Key Concept

Interactionism — a theory claiming that things in the world can truly cause changes in each other. For example, when you high-five me, you truly cause me to experience a stinging sensation in my hand.

Key Concept

Substance Dualism — a theory claiming that the mind (or soul) and body are two distinct and very different things.

Key Concept

Body — what it sounds like! The body is the physical part or aspect of a thing and has characteristics like shape, size, etc.

Key Concept

Soul — that part or aspect of a thing involving mental aspects of their existence, e.g., thoughts, feelings, decisions, etc. The “soul”, in this sense, is more or less just the mind.

Key Concept

Causal Interaction — When one thing acts (i.e., itself does something) and in so acting makes another thing change. For example, when you high-five me, you cause me to experience a stinging sensation in my hand.

Key Concept

God as God – The phrase “God as God” is basically a synonym for “God the subject.” In other words, it refers to God precisely in God’s status as an incomprehensible divine Other.

Key Concept

Incarnation – The Christian doctrine of the incarnation is the notion that the word of God became fully human in the person of Jesus of Nazareth. It is closely associated with the doctrine of the trinity, which asserts that God the Father, God the Son (Jesus as the word made flesh), and God the Holy Spirit are one God.

Key Concept

Religious Fanaticism – In Feuerbach’s use of the term, a religious fanatic is someone who is unwaveringly faithful to God as an utterly mysterious superhuman being. They subordinate other things—especially the love of other humans—to submission before this divine other.

Key Concept

God the Subject – When Feuerbach refers to God as a subject, he is referring to the commonplace religious belief that God is a being who has various attributes, like a loving nature.

Key Concept

Faith Separates Man From God – Faith separates God from man in this sense: it treats God as a mysterious other, a being radically distinct from us.

Key Concept

 Faith – Belief in and fidelity to a transcendent divine subject like God.

Key Concept

Orthodoxy – Orthodoxy refers to “right belief,” and it is concern with identifying heresies and ensuring that people believe and practice correctly.

Key Concept

Indirect Form of Self-Knowledge – Feuerbach’s view is that religious belief is a naive way of relating to our human nature and its perfections. It is naive or childlike because it treats these as external realities that belong to God. He believes a mature and contemplative person realizes these don’t belong to God, but rather to our species, abstractly conceived.

Key Concept

Above the Individual Man – The human perfections are “above the individual” insofar as no particular individual ever perfectly realizes them. They are abstractions.

Key Concept

Divine Trinity – Feuerbach is having fun here. He is using the theological phrasing of the Trinity to talk about human perfections. In calling reason, love, and freedom of the will “divine,” he means they are absolutely good; they are activities whose goodness is intrinsic to their practice or exercise. This isn’t a novel philosophical view. For example, Immanuel Kant argued that autonomy or a good will is the only thing which is unconditionally good.

Key Concept

Perfections – The end to which a faculty or power is ordered. For example, omniscience would be the perfection of the intellect. Traditionally, God is said to possess all perfections.

Key Concept

Love – When Feuerbach writes about love, he is referring to unconditional concern for others and the desire for fellowship with them. He is here asserting that love, understood in this sense, is the perfect activity of the affective faculty. In other words, our feelings and passions are fully actualized and engaged in an intrinsically valuable activity when we genuinely love others.

Key Concept

Infinite – The infinite is whatever can be understood as unbounded or unlimited. Human nature in the abstract is unbounded and unlimited. It is only bounded or limited in its concrete form as it is realized by particular material individuals.

Key Concept

Higher Consciousness – The sort of consciousness that mature human beings possess, but which other animals do not. It is “higher” than animal consciousness because it involves thinking abstractly about the form or essence of things.

Key Concept

Science – Feuerbach uses the term science in its classical sense, meaning systematically organized knowledge. Any body of knowledge founded on an understanding of first principles and the essences of things is a science in this sense.

Key Concept

Popular Sovereignty – The view that a government’s authority to rule comes from the people, making a ruler subject to the will of their citizens.

Key Concept

The Divine Right of Kings – The theory that kings are chosen by God and thus that political revolt is a rebellion against the will of God.

Key Concept

Synthesis – The prefix ‘syn-’ means “together,” so a synthesis “brings together” or combines elements of both a thesis and its antithesis.

Key Concept

Antithesis– An antithesis is the contradiction of a thesis. For example, internationalism could be understood as the antithesis of nationalism.

Key Concept

Thesis – In Hegelian terms, a thesis can be understood as a position or theory. Examples include any of the “-isms” that we discuss in science, history, and philosophy, such as Darwinism, capitalism, nationalism, etc.

Key Concept

Progressor’s Temptation – a unique temptation for those making progress in which pride impedes their further progress and leads to backsliding.

Key Concept

Progressors – those who are not yet expert Stoic practitioners, but who are also aware of the fact that they must change their lives in that direction. They are working on making progress.

Key Concept

Intellectualism – the philosophical view that our motivations and emotions are all judgments. The reason why you do something, your motivation, is because you believe it’s the right thing to do. The reason why you feel good or bad about something, an emotion, is because you believe that something good or bad happened to you.

Key Concept

Duties – acts of service, obedience, and respect that we owe to each other. The duties we owe to each other depend on what kind of relationship we have.

Key Concept

Askeses – exercises of Stoic thought and practice that make the lessons and habits of Stoic philosophy second-nature for Stoic practitioners.

Key Concept

Externals – things that are not under our control but that are all-too-easily confused with things that should be important to us, like wealth, status, and pleasure. Too many people believe externals like these are necessary for the good life, and the Stoic path is to focus not on these things but rather what is up to us. 

Key Concept

The Fundamental Division – the division between things that are under our direct control and those that are not. The important lesson is to care only about the things we can control.

Key Concept

The Greatest Happiness Principle – A principle which says that actions are right insofar as they promote happiness and wrong insofar as they promote unhappiness

Key Concept

Higher and Lower Pleasures – Types of pleasures that differ in terms of their quality. Things like food and drugs create lower pleasures. Things like intellectual pursuits and doing the right thing create higher forms of pleasure.

Key Concept

The Doctrine of Swine – An objection that utilitarianism entails that if people would be happy rolling in mud, that’s what would be morally best for them to do, so we should reject the theory.

Key Concept

Utilitarianism – A normative theory of which actions are right or wrong. Utilitarianism says the right action is that which maximises utility.

Key Concept

Jeremy Bentham – Considered by some as the father of utilitarianism, Bentham was a moral philosopher and one of John Stuart Mill’s teachers

Key Concept

Epicurus – an ancient Greek philosopher and one of the first to advocate that the ultimate good is experiencing pleasure and avoiding pain.

Key Concept

Utility – The thing that is ultimately valuable in itself. For Mill, this is happiness, which he then understands as pleasure and the absence of pain.

Key Concept

Contract Theory – a modern political theory identifying consent as the sole justification for government. Contract theory is associated with Thomas Hobbes (1588-1679), John Locke (1632-1704), Jean Jacques Rousseau (1712-1778), and more recently, John Rawls (1921-2002)

Key Concept

Prejudice – a foundational, strongly held, unreasoned (but not necessarily irrational) moral opinion or belief. We might believe, for example, that parents have special obligations towards their own children.

Key Concept

A Priori – a philosophical term of art meaning (in Latin) “prior to experience,” which refers to knowledge that is innate or arrived at purely through reasoning, like the truths of mathematics.

Key Concept

Rights – moral claims invoking immunity from (or entitlement to) some specific treatment (or good) from others. Commonly recognized rights include the right to free speech or the right to healthcare. 

Key Concept

Reform – a change in the social order that originates from the existing character of society. An example would be market-based healthcare reform in a capitalist society.

Key Concept

Conservatism – a modern political ideology that aims to preserve and promote the existing (or traditional)  institutions of society. These institutions typically include the rule of law, property, the family, and religion. 

Key Concept

Contingent Being – A being that can fail to exist. Its existence is not guaranteed. This being might come to exist or it might not.

Key Concept

Necessary Being – A being that can’t fail to exist. Its non-existence is impossible. This also means that such a being has always existed.

Key Concept

Want to read more about why the infinite regress option doesn’t work in the Second Way? Check out Sean Floyd’s entry in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

Key Concept

Efficient Cause – An efficient cause is something that directly makes another thing exist or move. An example of this is when I kick a ball down a hill. I am the efficient cause of the ball rolling down the hill because I make it move down the hill.

Key Concept

Infinite Regress: Begin with some fact. We begin to explain that fact by appealing to another fact, where these facts are related by either causality or dependence. To create the regress, you keep appealing to more and more facts about causality and dependence without end.

Key Concept

Actuality – An ability or action something is currently exercising. Imagine that I am sitting comfortably at my desk, and then I stand up to take a break from reading. In this case, I am now actually standing. 

Key Concept

Potentiality – What something has the capacity to do, but isn’t currently doing. Imagine I am sitting comfortably at my desk. Even though I’m not currently standing, I have the capacity to be standing. So, even while I’m not standing, I have the potential to stand. 

Key Concept

Theists and Non-Theists – A theist is someone who believes that God exists, while a non-theist does not. Non-theists include atheists, who believe that God does not exist, and agnostics, who are uncertain about whether God exists.

Key Concept

Glaucon – one of Plato’s brothers and one of Socrates’ main interlocutors in the Republic dialogue. In that dialogue, he challenges Socrates to provide a compelling justification for why one should be a just person beyond merely following conventions or avoiding punishment. This sets up Socrates’ defense of justice as intrinsically worthwhile. Throughout the Republic, Glaucon prods Socrates to fully explain his theories of the ideal society, philosopher-kings, and the Form of the Good.

Key Concept

Aristotle – a Greek philosopher (384-322 BC) who studied under Plato and went on to be one of the most influential philosophers to ever live. Simply called “The Philosopher” by Thomas Aquinas and others in the medieval period, Aristotle’s views would eventually be synthesized with Christian theology, laying the intellectual foundation for later scholarly developments in Western Europe.

Key Concept

Understanding – Socrates describes education as turning one’s “understanding” in the right direction. The word “understanding” here translates the ancient Greek term “to phronēsai,” which means “understanding,” “being conscious,” or “having insight.” People who are wicked focus their “understanding” on how best to accomplish their selfish and narrow desires. Those who are wise, in contrast, have learned to focus their “understanding” on what is truly good and beneficial.

Key Concept

The Form of the Good – Socrates characterizes the ultimate goal of education as coming to know “the Form of the Good.” The Form of the Good is his technical term for the meaning of goodness: what it is to be good. Socrates is clear that this “knowledge of the Good” is not simply theoretical knowledge, but also knowledge in the sense of “knowing how”: knowing how to achieve what’s good, to do what’s good, to accomplish what’s good. Mere “book knowledge” or simply being smart is not enough.

Key Concept

The Intelligible – Socrates uses “the intelligible” to name the aspects of the world that we can only grasp through thinking or insight. With my eyes I can see the tree outside my window, but what it means to be a tree is something I can only comprehend in thought. Likewise, I can see the people around me, but human nature, human dignity, and what it means to be human is something I can only grasp conceptually. “The intelligible” is the world insofar as it “makes sense” and can be comprehended.

Key Concept

The Visible – By “the visible,” Socrates means those aspects of the world we can perceive with our five senses and our imagination—those aspects of the world we can see, hear, taste, smell, touch, and imagine. For example, with my eyes I can see the sky, trees, people around me, and so on as visible things. “The visible” is the world insofar as it can be perceived and imagined. 

Key Concept

Education – Socrates says that the allegorical story he tells represents the effect of education on human nature. “Education” here is a translation of the ancient Greek word “paideia,” which means “education” in the widest sense of the term. “Paideia” doesn’t mean “education” in the sense of going to school or getting good grades. Instead, it refers to the process of becoming a wise, intelligent, good, and well-rounded human being.

Key Concept

Allegory – An allegory is a symbolic narrative where characters, events, and/or settings represent abstract ideas or convey deeper meanings beyond the literal story. Socrates tells such a symbolic narrative in the passages below. The characters, events, and setting of his narrative symbolize the effect of what he calls “education.” 

Key Concept

Self-knowledge – Knowledge of the contents of one’s own mind, such as one’s own beliefs and desires. Self-knowledge can be gained through introspection, that is, by reflecting on what one thinks and experiences. Some philosophers believe that self-knowledge has special properties that our knowledge of the external world lacks, such as being clearer, more reliable, or more valuable.

Key Concept

Dualism – The view that the mind is entirely distinct from the body. This view is usually contrasted with different kinds of monism, which hold that the mind is ultimately just a part of the body (materialism) or that the body is ultimately just a part of the mind (idealism). Dualists hold that the mind and the body are fundamentally different aspects of reality, and both categories are needed to properly describe the universe, especially the human person. 

Key Concept

The Self – What the ‘I’ in ‘I am, I exist’ refers to; the part of you that really makes you you. Many philosophers have provided rich accounts of what the self ultimately is, including the soul, the mind, one special feature of the mind (such as consciousness), a mixture of all these elements, or perhaps a mere illusion.  

Key Concept

The ‘Cogito’ – Descartes’ famous claim ‘I think, therefore I am’ is often referred to as the cogito. The name comes from the Latin rendering of this phrase, which is ‘cogito, ergo sum.’ Descartes held that one can always believe this proposition with certainty. We cannot doubt our own existence, so the cogito survives his exercise of intense doubt. The cogito appears several times in Descartes’ writings, and he often phrased it slightly differently each time. It appears in the Second Meditation as ‘I am, I exist.’

Key Concept

Certainty – When one believes something with certainty, one is maximally confident that it is true. A certainty is something that is beyond dispute or immune to doubt. Although this captures the basic idea, like many epistemological notions, clarifying precisely what the notion of certainty amounts to is an ongoing area of philosophical research. 

Key Concept

Vice – A bad habit that we learn over time through instruction or instinct and that we develop through repetition. What makes the habit bad is that, once we have that habit, our tendency is to do the incorrect thing in certain types of situations. We may choose to do something entirely uncalled for in that situation, or we may act at the wrong time, in the wrong way, to the wrong degree, or with the wrong attitudes, or for the wrong reasons.

Key Concept

Relative Mean – The “Goldilocks amount” of some type of action or emotion. When you act in this way, according to Aristotle, you act exactly as is required under the current circumstances. This means that you do what is called for by the situation at hand, rather than doing something too extreme or not doing something extreme enough. You do something in the moderate amount (the mean amount) relative to the specific situation you are in when you need to act.

Key Concept

Excellence/Virtue – A good habit that we learn over time through instruction and repetition. What makes the habit good is that, once we have that habit, we have a strong tendency to do the right thing at the right time, in the right way, to the right degree, with the right attitudes, whenever we are confronted with a situation that we know calls us to exercise that habit.

Key Concept

Doxastic Voluntarism – the view that we have at least some control over what we believe.

Key Concept

Evidence – information that increases the probability that a claim is true.

Key Concept

Sufficient – enough of something for a particular purpose. Whether something is sufficient is context-dependent.

Key Concept

Solon – In the Histories of Herodotus, Solon visits Croesus, the king of Lydia. Even though Croesus shows Solon all of his wealth, Solon refuses to call him the happiest man who ever lived because he does not know how Croesus will die

Key Concept

Priam – According to Greek mythology, Priam was the final king of Troy during the Trojan War. Despite his wealth and political power, he was killed by Achilles’ son Neopotolemus during the Sack of Troy

Key Concept

Virtue – The consistent and reliable tendency to perform one’s function excellently. When a person has a certain virtue, like courage, they have spent time developing the habit, in this case reacting to danger well, using their human abilities. The virtues then make it possible for us to live a life of flourishing

Key Concept

Sardanapalus – An Assyrian king described by the historian Diodorus as living a life of extreme decadence. Sardanapalus indulged himself with food, alcohol, and many concubines, even going so far to say that physical gratification is the purpose of life. Chrysippus said that, on his tomb is inscribed the following: “Though knowing full well that thou art but mortal, indulge thy desire, find joy in thy feasts. Dead, thou shalt have no delight […] I have only what I have eaten, what wantonness I have committed, what joys I received through passion; but my many rich possessions are now utterly dissolved.”

Key Concept

Function – the characteristic activity of a given thing which makes it what it is. The function of a knife is cutting, while the function of a heart is to pump blood

Key Concept

Eudaimonia – Frequently translated as ‘happiness’, eudaimonia means the attainment of active human flourishing, and is the end Aristotle identifies as humanity’s highest final good

Key Concept

Final Good – A good that we pursue for its own sake. Common examples of final goods include happiness, knowledge, and friendship

Key Concept

Instrumental Good – A good that we pursue for the sake of some other good. A common example is money, as money allows us to purchase other kinds of goods

Key Concept

Anytus – an Athenian politician, war general, and  one of the primary accusers behind Socrates’ prosecution. Anytus feared that Socrates would undermine the young Athenian democracy he had helped create and defend

Key Concept

Oracle of Delphi – the high priestess at the temple at Delphi, the oracle was one of the most sought after seers of the ancient world and was thought to relay messages from the god Apollo

Key Concept

Chaerephon – an ancient Greek from the city Sphettus, Chaerephon is remembered as a loyal friend of Socrates, also making an appearance in two other Platonic dialogues, the Charmides and the Gorgias

Key Concept

Meletus – A poet and citizen of Athens and one of Socrates’ accusers. Amongst other things, Meletus accused Socrates of corrupting the youth

Key Concept

Apollo – the ancient sacred site Delphi was dedicated to the god Apollo, an ancient Greek god and the god that Socrates refers to throughout the Apology

Key Concept

Virtue – a character trait, acquired through habitual practice, that enables one to act well. The virtues can also be thought of as excellences of human character, as they make it possible for us to live a life of flourishing. Examples of the virtues include courage, prudence, and justice

Key Concept

The Evil Demon Argument – Argues that we cannot hold any of our beliefs with certainty because we could be radically deceived by an evil demon. A classic argument given by Descartes for doubting the reliability of almost all of our beliefs

Key Concept

Philosophical Skepticism – The position that we do not know many things that we ordinarily take ourselves to know

Key Concept

A Posteriori Knowledge – Knowledge that can only be acquired through having particular, concrete experiences. Such knowledge can be gained simply through our everyday experiences, or through more complex means like controlled scientific experiments

Key Concept

A Priori Knowledge – Knowledge that can be gained without having any particular concrete experiences. Such knowledge is typically gained by rational insight or intuition

Key Concept

Cartesian Method of DoubtA process employed by René Descartes of rejecting all beliefs that he had at least some reason to doubt in order to see if he had any beliefs that he could know with certainty

Key Concept

Revelation – Theological truths that have been made known by means of some religious text, testimony, authority, or experience, or the act or process in which such truths are made known.

Key Concept

Rationalism – The view that the only reliable means of coming to know truths about God is reason. As a result, what we might otherwise believe by means of faith ought to be disregarded or even rejected in favor of what we must believe by means of reason.

Key Concept

Fideism – The view that the only reliable means of coming to know truths about God is faith. As a result, what we might otherwise believe by means of reason ought to be disregarded or even rejected in favor of what we must believe by means of faith.

Key Concept

Faith – The act of accepting a proposition as true for which there is less than demonstrable evidence, which rises above mere opinion but falls short of logical or scientific demonstration. Faith can also refer to a particular religious tradition or the body of beliefs that are central to that religious tradition.

Key Concept

Virtue – a character trait, acquired through habitual practice, that enables one to act well. The virtues can also be thought of as excellences of human character, as they make it possible for us to live a life of flourishing. Examples of the virtues include courage, prudence, and justice

Key Concept

Socratic Ignorance – an awareness of one’s own ignorance, and the reason that Socrates was deemed wise by the Oracle of Delphi. A person who lacks Socratic Ignorance may believe they know many things they actually don’t, leading them to overestimate how well they understand the world

Key Concept

Apologya formal defense of justification of an action or belief. A Christian apologist, for example, is someone who defends their faith and seeks to justify it through an appeal to reason.

Historical Connection

Solon’s Warning

In the Histories of Herodotus, Solon visits Croesus, the king of Lydia. Even though Croesus shows Solon all of his wealth, Solon refuses to call him the happiest man who ever lived because he does not know how Croesus will die

Historical Connection

Priam

According to Greek mythology, Priam was the final king of Troy during the Trojan War. Despite his wealth and political power, he was killed by Achilles’ son Neopotolemus during the Sack of Troy